“De l’esprit classique,” note 1 to “Trois idées politiques,” Romantisme et Révolution (Paris: Nouvelle Libraire Nationale, 1922), pp. 269–70. My translation. A short, lapidary exposition of Maurras’ conception of the classicism–romanticism dichotomy. His analysis owes much to Pierre Lasserre. Here Maurras represents the more straightforwardly political side of the classicist current within conservative-revolutionary thought, Lasserre and T. E. Hulme representing the middle term, and T. S. Eliot giving probably the most influential and most straightforwardly aesthetic formulation.
PDF: https://www.academia.edu/45025240/Charles_Maurras_On_the_Classical_Spirit_1922_
A deplorable error, due
perhaps to the prejudices of the professor or the former student, led our
master Taine to designate as classical the spirit that prepared the way for Revolution.
On reflection, classical Antiquity played but a minute part in it. As far as
classical books are concerned, the Revolutionary bibliography includes hardly
more than Plato’s Republic and
Plutarch’s Parallel Lives; nor would
these be present had not the Father and Doctor of revolutionary ideas, Jean-Jacques
Rousseau, borrowed from them more language than substance.
Plutarch was well aware of Semitic ideas, before being compromised despite himself; for he was born almost at the very moment that a wind from the East altered the great soul of Antiquity. As for Plato, he is, of all Greek sages, the one who imported the most and the most singular ideas from Asia; more than any of his confrères he was discussed and disfigured by Alexandrian Jewry. What we call Platonism, and what we might call Plutarchism, would, in isolation, representing the wisdom of Athens and Rome rather poorly; there are parts of these two doctrines not so much Graeco-Latin as barbarian, and already “romantic.”
But with her physicists
and geometers, with her sophists, her artists, her poets and her logicians,
with Phidias, with Aristotle, who accessed a new world, one might say that
ancient Greece laid the foundations of positive science, philosophy and
religion; with her statesmen, her historians and her moralists, ancient Rome expounded
so powerful a lesson in realist politics that neither English Parliament nor
Capetian Monarchy have surpassed her. Neither in the family nor in the city of
the Ancients was anything left to Anarchy; the caprice of leaders and the
prescriptions of laws precisely temper and balance one another. The institution
of slavery relieves democracy of its greatest difficulties; and, furthermore,
the sad tale of the last half-century of Athenian liberty, the repeated
observations of Aristophanes, of Xenophon, even of Plato, and of every master
of the Attic genius, the rapidity of the consumption, the dazzling glitter of
the fall are major testimonies in favour of aristocracies and of other regimes
of authority. Who learns of it will feel rather ill-disposed towards the dogma
of popular government.
In the modern era,
Catholic philosophy preferred to model itself upon Aristotle; Catholic politics
appropriated the methods of Roman politics. Such is the character of the
classical tradition. The classical spirit is precisely the essence of the
doctrines of higher humanity. It is a spirit of authority and aristocracy. To
call the spirit of the Revolution classical is to strip a word of its natural
sense and to prepare misunderstandings.
The Revolution comes from
quite another quarter: the Bible of the Reformation; the statutes of the
Republic of Geneva; Calvinist theologians; the old individualist ferment of
Germany, of which trilingual Switzerland served as the European vector;
ultimately personal outbursts of a sensibility restrained not by hereditary moeurs, nor by strict discipline, nor by
healthy reason: these are the lowly causes of the ideas that arose in the mind
of Rousseau. By the magic of eloquence, they entered old French society with
him; far from engendering any classical cast of mind, they moved to destroy
that spirit of progress and of order. Who would deny Rousseau to have opened
the romantic era?
Precisely because Taine
is entitled to our respect, it is fitting to note that one cannot admit a
certain detail of his vocabulary, and why one even has the duty to contest it.
No comments:
Post a Comment